Online Read Free Novel
  • Home
  • Romance & Love
  • Fantasy
  • Science Fiction
  • Mystery & Detective
  • Thrillers & Crime
  • Actions & Adventure
  • History & Fiction
  • Horror
  • Western
  • Humor

    Anger and Forgiveness

    Page 4
    Prev Next


      “ego- identity.”14 Like Smith’s account and mine, Lazarus’s treatment

      emphasizes that causes and principles can be objects of emotions— but

      only when and if a person has ascribed personal importance to them.

      Anger is typically accompanied by a wide range of bodily changes

      and subjective feeling- states. Bodily changes of some type are always

      present when people are angry, and, after all, the thoughts involved in

      anger are themselves bodily changes.15 Subjective feelings of some type

      are typically present as well, but they are likely to be highly varied (both

      within a person at different times and across people), and they may be

      entirely absent if anger is not conscious. Just as the fear of death can lurk beneath the threshold of consciousness and yet influence conduct, so too

      with anger, in at least some cases. It is a familiar experience to become

      aware that one has been angry at someone for some time, and that this

      hidden anger has influenced one’s behavior.

      The bodily changes and subjective feelings often associated with

      anger, though important in their way, have too little constancy for them

      to be included in the definition of anger, as necessary conditions of that

      emotion.16 For some people, anger feels like boiling in the neighborhood

      of the heart (as Aristotle says). For others, it may feel like a throbbing

      Anger

      17

      in the temples or a pain at the back of the neck. And in some cases it

      simply is not felt, like a lurking fear of death. One job of therapy is to

      discover hidden anger. Although at times the therapeutic process (badly

      managed) manufactures anger where it was not present before, there are

      surely many cases of genuine discovery.

      III. Elements of Anger

      What is anger’s distinctive content? A good starting point is Aristotle’s

      definition. Although it will turn out to be too narrow to cover all cases of

      anger, it helps us dissect its elements.17

      Anger, Aristotle holds, is “a desire accompanied by pain for an imag-

      ined retribution on account of an imagined slighting inflicted by people

      who have no legitimate reason to slight oneself or one’s own” ( Rhetoric

      1378a31– 33). Anger, then, involves

      1. Slighting or down- ranking ( oligōria)

      2. Of the self or people close to the self

      3. Wrongfully or inappropriately done ( mē prosēkontōn)

      4. Accompanied by pain

      5. Involving a desire for retribution

      By twice repeating “imagined” ( phainomenēs), Aristotle emphasizes that what is relevant to the emotion is the way the situation is seen from the

      angry person’s viewpoint, not the way it really is, which might, of course,

      be different.

      Anger is an unusually complex emotion, since it involves both pain

      and pleasure: Aristotle shortly says that the prospect of retribution is

      pleasant. He does not clarify the causal relationships involved, but we

      can easily see that the pain is supposed to be produced by the injury,

      and the desire for retribution somehow responds to the injury. Moreover,

      anger also involves a double reference— to a person or people and to

      an act. Using non- Aristotelian terminology to make this issue explicit:

      the target of anger is typically a person, the one who is seen as having inflicted damage— and as having done so wrongfully or illegitimately. “I

      am angry at so- and- so.” And the focus of anger is an act imputed to the target, which is taken to be a wrongful damage.18

      Injuries may be the focus in grief as well. But whereas grief focuses

      on the loss or damage itself, and lacks a target (unless it is the lost person, as in “I am grieving for so- and- so”), anger starts with the act that inflicted the damage, seeing it as intentionally inflicted by the target— and then, as

      a result, one becomes angry, and one’s anger is aimed at the target. Anger,

      then, requires causal thinking, and some grasp of right and wrong.19

      18

      Anger and Forgiveness

      The damage may be inflicted on the person who, as a result, feels anger,

      or it may be inflicted on some other person or thing within that person’s

      circle of concern.

      The least puzzling parts of Aristotle’s definition, from the vantage

      point of contemporary intuitions, are its emphasis on pain and its empha-

      sis on wrongful damage. How exactly does the wrongful act of another

      cause pain to the self? Well, presumably, the person sees (or believes) that

      something about which she cares deeply has been damaged. The item

      damaged must, indeed, be seen as significant and not trivial, or pain will

      not be a consequence. This pain is, up to a point, not dissimilar to the pain felt in grief. It tracks the perceived size of the damage. Nonetheless, the

      pain of anger typically makes internal reference, as well, to the (believed)

      wrongful act of another person: the pain of seeing one’s child mur-

      dered just feels different from that of losing a child to accidental death.

      (Aristotle often emphasizes that pleasure and pain themselves have an

      intentional content: the pain, then, is pain at the injury that has [as the person believes] been inflicted. It’s that specific sort of pain.)

      As for wrongful injury: even though we experience frustration when

      someone inadvertently damages us, we only become angry when we

      believe (rightly or wrongly) that the damage was inflicted by a person

      or persons, and in a manner that was illegitimate or wrongful. Lazarus

      gives the example of a store clerk who ignores a customer because he

      is busy talking on the phone. The customer will feel wrongly slighted,

      but if she learns that the reason for the phone call was a medical emer-

      gency involving the clerk’s child, she will no longer be angry, because she

      will see that it was legitimate to give the phone call priority.20 We aren’t

      always so reasonable, of course, but what matters is how we see the situ-

      ation: we are angry only if we see the damage as illegitimate. (This need not be a notion of moral wrong: just some type of wrongfulness.)

      Notoriously, however, people sometimes get angry when they are

      frustrated by inanimate objects, which presumably cannot act wrong-

      fully. This sort of behavior was reported already by the Stoic philoso-

      pher Chrysippus, who spoke of people biting their keys and kicking

      their door when it doesn’t open right away, and hurling a stone against

      which one has stubbed one’s toe, all the while “saying the most inap-

      propriate things.”21 In 1988, the Journal of the American Medical Association published an article on “vending machine rage”: fifteen injuries, three of

      them fatal, as a result of angry men22 kicking or rocking machines that

      had taken their money without dispensing the drink. (The fatal injuries

      were caused by machines falling over on the men and crushing them.)23

      Do such familiar reactions show that anger does not require the idea of

      wrongful damage? I see no reason to think this. We tend to think that

      we have a right to expect “respect” and cooperation from the inanimate

      Anger

      19

      objects that serve our ends, and in the moment we react as if they were

      bad people, since they clearly are not doing “their job” for us. We quickly

      reali
    ze that this doesn’t make sense— most of the time.

      Butler suggests that there can be a species of anger, “sudden anger,”

      when something thwarts or opposes us, and that this type does not require

      the thought of a wrong.24 I doubt, however, that Butler has actually iden-

      tified a distinct species of anger. Suddenness by itself will not do that: for once judgments of value become deeply internalized, we will become

      angry very quickly at a wrongful attack on what we love. When someone

      pulls a gun on your child, you don’t stop to think. Nor is it obvious that

      angry people are aware that a “thwarting” is not a real wrong: consider

      those vending machines. At most, we should concede to Butler that there

      may be a type of anger that is inchoate, prior to full- fledged causal think-

      ing and thus prior to a real judgment of wrong. Infants, for example, fly

      into a rage when their needs are not met. And yet our increasing knowl-

      edge of the cognitive sophistication of young infants makes it plausible to

      ascribe a vague inchoate judgment of the form, “I ought to have this, and

      my parent is withholding it.”25 On the whole then, with some borderline

      cases in early infancy, Aristotle’s insistence on wrong holds up.26

      More problematic, at least initially, is Aristotle’s restriction to

      “oneself or one’s own”: for surely we may have anger when a cause

      or principle one cares about has been wrongfully assailed, or when a

      stranger is the victim of an unjust aggression. Yes indeed, but that (claims

      the Aristotelian) is because in that case it has become part of one’s circle

      of concern. In other words, “oneself or one’s own” is just a way of allud-

      ing to the eudaimonistic structure that anger shares with other emotions.

      This response seems correct: just as we grieve not about every death in

      the world, but only the death of those who are dear to us, so we get angry

      not at any and every instance of wrongdoing in the world, but only those

      that touch on core values of the self. As with other emotions, a vivid epi-

      sode may jump- start the response by moving a distant object into the

      circle of concern. If, instead of Adam Smith’s tale of an earthquake in

      China (which jump- starts compassion), we hear a vivid tale of a genocide

      in a distant country, then we may be aroused to anger on behalf of the

      slaughtered people, even if they were not antecedently of concern to us.

      But Smith’s point holds: so long as the emotion lasts, so long those people

      have to be of concern to us. If the concern ceases (because, for example,

      we become diverted by pressing concerns closer to ourselves), so does

      the emotion.

      More problematic still is Aristotle’s reference to a “slighting” or

      “down- ranking.” We immediately associate this with the values of an

      honor culture, where people are always ranking themselves against

      one another, and where the central case of wrongdoing is indeed a

      20

      Anger and Forgiveness

      down- ranking. Surely, we are inclined to say, many damages involve cher-

      ished projects without being seen as diminutions of status. Subsequent

      Greco-

      Roman philosophy modifies Aristotle’s condition, as I have

      already done. Seneca defines anger in terms of a “wrongful harm,” rather

      than a “slighting.”27 The canonical Stoic definition speaks of a belief that

      one has been wronged.28

      Has Aristotle simply made a mistake? I shall argue that he has, but

      not as large a mistake as one might think: he has captured a style of think-

      ing that is very common in anger, though not omnipresent.

      First, the mistake. Defenders of Aristotle try to defend his definition

      by referring, once again, to eudaimonism. Thus Lazarus, attempting to

      give a general definition, and not one pertaining only to honor cultures,

      applauds Aristotle’s definition, because it captures this very general idea

      of an injury to the self’s cherished projects.

      Lazarus’s defense, however, is clumsy. Not every eudaimonistic

      injury (meaning injury to something seen by the agent as important)

      involves a personal down- ranking. Injuries to causes or principles are

      typically eudaimonistic without involving the thought of a low ranking

      of the self. Even when anger’s focus is an injury to a beloved person, the

      angry person usually does not think that the damager is trying to belittle

      her. She has a sense of eudaimonistic injury (the injury looms large from

      the viewpoint of her values and concerns), without a sense of personal

      diminution. So Aristotle’s account is too narrow.

      The idea of down- ranking proves more explanatorily fertile, how-

      ever, than we might at first suppose. There is something comical in the

      self- congratulatory idea that honor cultures are in another time or at least another place (such as, putatively, the Middle East), given the obsessive

      attention paid by Americans to competitive ranking in terms of status,

      money, and other qualities. Even the idea that “honor killings” are an arti-

      fact of specific (Middle Eastern? Muslim?) cultures needs rethinking. The

      rate of intimate partner violence is slightly higher in Italy than in Jordan,29

      and we may safely say that a sense of manly honor and competitive injury

      is involved in many killings of women in many countries.30 Empirical

      psychologist Carol Tavris’s wide- ranging study of anger in America

      finds ubiquitous reference to “insults,” “slights,” “condescension,”

      “being treated as if I were of no account.”31 People remain intensely con-

      cerned about their standing, now as then, and they find endless occasions

      for anger in acts that seem to threaten it.

      From now on I shall call this sort of perceived down- ranking a

      status- injury. The very idea of a status- injury already includes the idea of wrongfulness, for, as Aristotle notes, diminution of status is usually voluntary: if someone acted accidentally, I won’t perceive that as diminish-

      ing my status. (Remember the store clerk who had an urgent phone call.)

      Anger

      21

      We should, however, broaden the scope of Aristotle’s account to include

      the many cases in which people behave in a denigrating or insulting way

      without being consciously aware that this is what they are doing. When

      the target of such behavior (status- related denigration in the workplace,

      for example) reacts with status anger, he need not think that his boss con-

      sciously intended the insult. But he probably does need to think some-

      thing else: that the remark is part of a pattern of belief and conduct, a

      policy regarding the status of employees, that the boss has adopted and

      for which he is accountable.

      Anger is not always, but very often, about status- injury. And status-

      injury has a narcissistic flavor: rather than focusing on the wrongful-

      ness of the act as such, a focus that might lead to concern for wrongful

      acts of the same type more generally, the status- angry person focuses

      obsessively on herself and her standing vis- à- vis others.

      In connection with such injuries, both Aristotle and Lazarus empha-

      size the relevance of personal insecurity or vulnerability: we are prone to


      anger to the extent that we feel insecure or lacking control with respect

      to the aspect of our goals that has been assailed— and to the extent that

      we expect or desire control. Anger aims at restoring lost control and often

      achieves at least an illusion of it.32 To the extent that a culture encourages people to feel vulnerable to affront and down- ranking in a wide variety

      of situations, it encourages the roots of status- focused anger.

      IV. Anger and Payback

      What is anger’s aim? The philosophical tradition concurs in holding that

      there is a double movement in the emotion; this double movement, from

      pain inflicted to striking back, is so prominent that ancient taxonomies

      classify anger as an emotion that looks forward to a future good, rather

      than as one that responds to a present bad— although, once they say more,

      they acknowledge that it has both aspects. Aristotle emphasizes that the

      forward movement characteristic of anger is pleasant, and that anger is in

      that sense constructive and linked to hope. The imagined payback is seen

      as somehow assuaging the pain or making good the damage.33

      But how exactly does this work? How does pain lead to the sort of

      lashing out, or striking back, that we associate with anger in at least many

      cases? And why would someone who has been gravely wounded look

      forward with hope to doing something unwelcome to the offender? If

      we had a non- cognitive account of anger, there would be nothing further

      to say: that is just the way hardwired mechanisms work. But ours is not

      that type of account, so we must try to understand this puzzle. For it is

      a puzzle. Doing something to the offender does not bring dead people

      22

      Anger and Forgiveness

      back to life, heal a broken limb, or undo a sexual violation. So why do

      people somehow believe that it does? Or what, exactly, do they believe

      that makes even a little sense of their retaliatory project?

      First, however, we had better make sure that the philosophical tra-

      dition is correct in holding that a wish for payback is a conceptual part

      of anger. It is pretty impressive that so many first- rate thinkers, from

      Aristotle and the Stoics to Butler and Smith to recent empirical psycholo-

     


    Prev Next
Online Read Free Novel Copyright 2016 - 2025