Online Read Free Novel
  • Home
  • Romance & Love
  • Fantasy
  • Science Fiction
  • Mystery & Detective
  • Thrillers & Crime
  • Actions & Adventure
  • History & Fiction
  • Horror
  • Western
  • Humor

    Anger and Forgiveness

    Page 2
    Prev Next


      dichotomy is too simple, since the intense love and trust of intimate rela-

      tionships may still give legitimate occasions for painful emotions such as

      grief and fear, whether or not law has stepped in.) As Aristotle will later

      say, the gentle- tempered person (his name for the virtue in the area of

      anger) is not vengeful, but, instead, inclined to sympathetic understand-

      ing.15 Law gives a double benefit: it keeps us safe without, and it permits

      us to care for one another, unburdened by retributive anger, within.

      Notice, in particular, that law permits us to care about wrongs done

      to friends and family members, without spending our lives consumed

      with angry emotion and projects of retribution. Most of the anger in the

      pre- law world that Aeschylus depicts had little to do with the actual liv-

      ing people: it tracked past wrongs done to long- ago ancestors, or, occa-

      sionally, one’s parents or relatives. Thus the Agamemnon opens with the

      Introduction

      5

      past, in the form of the Chorus’s anguished depiction of the long- ago

      slaughter of Iphigeneia— which Clytemnestra will shortly avenge. And

      as soon as Aegisthus enters, late in the play, rather than speaking at all

      about himself or what he cares about, he launches into the gruesome

      saga of his father Thyestes, who was duped into eating the flesh of his

      own children by Agamemnon’s father Atreus. People don’t get to exist as

      themselves: they are in thrall to a past that burdens them. Anger about

      wrongs done to oneself is transformed by law too, as we shall see, but

      perhaps the largest change law effects is to give people a way of car-

      ing about others that does not involve exhausting vicarious retributive

      projects.16

      This book is not about ancient Greek ethics, but it takes its inspira-

      tion from the Aeschylean picture I have just sketched— from the idea that

      political justice offers a thoroughgoing transformation of the moral senti-

      ments in both the personal and the public realms. But I shall go further

      than Aeschylus, arguing that anger is always normatively problematic,

      whether in the personal or in the public realm.17 At the heart of my argu-

      ment is an analysis of anger, which I present in chapter 2. Concurring

      with a long philosophical tradition that includes Aristotle, the Greek and

      Roman Stoics, and Bishop Butler, I argue that anger includes, concep-

      tually, not only the idea of a serious wrong done to someone or some-

      thing of significance, but also the idea that it would be a good thing if

      the wrongdoer suffered some bad consequences somehow. Each of these

      thoughts must be qualified in complex ways, but that’s the essence of the

      analysis. I then argue that anger, so understood, is always normatively

      problematic in one or the other of two possible ways.

      One way, which I call the road of payback, makes the mistake of thinking that the suffering of the wrongdoer somehow restores, or contributes to

      restoring, the important thing that was damaged. That road is norma-

      tively problematic because the beliefs involved are false and incoherent,

      ubiquitous though they are. They derive from deep- rooted but misleading

      ideas of cosmic balance, and from people’s attempt to recover control in

      situations of helplessness. But the wrongdoer’s suffering does not bring

      back the person or valued item that was damaged. At most it may deter

      future offending and incapacitate the offender: but this is not all that the

      person taking the road of payback believes and seeks.

      There is one case, however, in which the beliefs involved in anger

      make a lot of sense, indeed all too much sense. That is the case that I shall call the road of status. If the victim sees the injury as about relative status and only about that— seeing it as a “down- ranking” of the victim’s

      self, as Aristotle put it— then indeed it does turn out to be the case that

      payback of some sort can be really efficacious. Lowering the status of

      the wrongdoer by pain or humiliation does indeed put me relatively up.

      6

      Anger and Forgiveness

      But then there is a different problem: it is normatively problematic to

      focus exclusively on relative status, and that type of obsessive narrow-

      ness, though common enough, is something we ought to discourage in

      both self and others.

      That’s the core of my main argument in a nutshell, but of course all

      these ideas must be unpacked and defended. Anger may still have some

      limited usefulness as a signal to self and/ or others that wrongdoing has taken place, as a source of motivations to address it, and as a deterrent to others, discouraging their aggression. Its core ideas, however, are profoundly flawed: either incoherent in the first case, or normatively ugly

      in the second.

      I then arrive at a crucial concept that I call the Transition. Most average people get angry. But often, noting the normative irrationality of anger,

      particularly in its payback mode, a reasonable person shifts off the ter-

      rain of anger toward more productive forward- looking thoughts, asking

      what can actually be done to increase either personal or social welfare.

      I explore the course of reflection that leads to this future- directed think-

      ing, which I prefer. (I interpret the transition undergone by the Furies to

      be this type of Transition, but that is not essential to my argument.) The

      Transition is a path that can be followed by an individual, but it may also

      be, as in Aeschylus, an evolutionary path for a society.

      I also recognize a borderline case of genuinely rational and norma-

      tively appropriate anger that I call Transition- Anger, whose entire content is: “How outrageous. Something should be done about that.” This

      forward- looking emotion, however, is less common, in that pure form,

      than one might suppose: most real- life cases of Transition- Anger are

      infected with the payback wish.

      In the core chapter and subsequent chapters, armed with this analysis,

      I then tackle three commonplaces about anger that bulk large in the phil-

      osophical literature, as well as in everyday life:

      1. Anger is necessary (when one is wronged) to the protection of dignity

      and self- respect.

      2. Anger at wrongdoing is essential to taking the wrongdoer seriously

      (rather than treating him or her like a child or a person of diminished

      responsibility).

      3. Anger is an essential part of combatting injustice.

      I grant that anger is sometimes instrumentally useful in the three ways

      I have mentioned. But this limited usefulness does not remove its nor-

      mative inappropriateness. Nor is it as useful, even in these roles, as it is

      sometimes taken to be.

      Four subsequent chapters (4, 5, 6, and 7) develop this core argument

      further in four distinct domains of life. A good inquiry into these matters

      Introduction

      7

      should distinguish several different realms of human interaction, asking

      carefully what human relations are proper to each, and what virtues are

      proper to each of these relations. The realm of deep personal affection

      (whether familial or friendly) is distinct from the political realm; it has

      distinct virtues and norms, where anger and judgment a
    re concerned.

      My argument will be structured around this division of realms.

      First, in chapter 4, I investigate the role of anger in intimate personal

      relationships, where it is often thought that anger, though sometimes

      excessive or misguided, is a valuable assertion of self- respect, and that it should be cultivated, particularly by people (and women are the example

      so often given) who are inclined to have a deficient sense of their own

      worth. I argue against this line of thinking, suggesting that the values

      distinctive of personal intimacy not only do not require anger but are

      deeply threatened by it. Of course serious damages and breaches of trust

      do occur, and they are often occasions for short- term anger and long- term

      grief. But grief for a loss is preferable, I shall argue, to an ongoing determination to pin the loss on someone else— both instrumentally, being bet-

      ter for the self, and intrinsically, being more appropriate to the nature of

      loving human relations. Though short- term anger is understandable and

      human, it is rarely helpful, and it certainly should not dictate the course

      of the future.

      I next investigate (in chapter 5) what I shall call a “Middle Realm,”

      the realm of the multitude of daily transactions we have with people and

      social groups who are not our close friends and are also not our political

      institutions or their official agents. A great deal of resentment is gener-

      ated in the Middle Realm, from slights to reputation to that unpardon-

      able sin— mentioned already by Aristotle— in which someone forgets

      your name. In this realm, I make a different argument from the one

      I advance for the intimate realm, where I recommend strong emotional

      upset, albeit grief and not anger. Here, I argue that the Roman Stoics,

      whose culture was unusually disfigured by resentments in the Middle

      Realm, are entirely correct: the right attitude is to get to a point where

      one understands how petty all these slights are, and one not only doesn’t

      get angry but also does not grieve. The damage simply is not serious

      enough. Seneca never quite got there, but he records his self- struggle in a

      way that offers good guidance. (Thus I shall be following Adam Smith in

      holding that the Stoics give sound advice except when they tell us not to

      care deeply for our loved ones, family, and friends.)

      But that cannot be the entire story, for of course, although a great deal

      of daily anger does deal with trivia such as insults and incompetence,

      sometimes damages in the Middle Realm are extremely serious: stranger-

      rape, murder by strangers, and so forth. These cases are not like the petty

      irritations and insults with which Stoic texts and daily life are typically

      8

      Anger and Forgiveness

      filled. Here is where the insights of Aeschylus become so important.

      In such a case, the thing to do is to turn matters over to the law, which

      should deal with them without anger and in a forward- looking spirit.

      Although serious matters in the personal realm may also be turned over

      to law, they leave, and appropriately so, a residue of deep emotion (grief,

      fear, compassion) that are integral to a relationship of love and trust. In

      the Middle Realm, by contrast, there is no point to any ongoing relation-

      ship with the malefactor, and law can assume the full burden of dealing

      with the wrong.

      I turn next to the Political Realm. In this realm, the primary virtue is

      impartial justice, a benevolent virtue that looks to the common good. It

      is first and foremost a virtue of institutions, but it is also, importantly, if derivatively, a virtue of the people who inhabit and support these institutions. But what sentiments animate and support justice? Here, once

      again, it is often held that anger is important, as a sentiment vindicating

      the equal dignity of the oppressed and expressing respect for the human

      being as an end. I divide my treatment of the Political Realm into two

      parts: everyday justice ( chapter 6) and revolutionary justice ( chapter 7).

      In the case of everyday justice I shall argue that the pursuit of justice

      is ill- served by a narrow focus on punishment of any type, but especially

      ill-served by criminal law retributivism, even of a sophisticated sort.

      Above all, society should take an ex ante perspective, analyzing the whole problem of crime and searching for the best strategies to address it going

      forward. Such strategies may certainly include punishment of offend-

      ers, but as just one part of a much larger project that would also include

      nutrition, education, health care, housing, employment, and much more.

      Although I shall not be able to carry out, here, the wide inquiry into social welfare that is really demanded, I offer at least an idea of what it would

      look like, and I then look more narrowly at criminal punishment as one

      tiny sliver of that enterprise.

      But what about revolutionary justice? Here it is often believed that

      anger can be both noble and essential, helping the oppressed to assert

      themselves and pursue justice. I argue, however, following the theo-

      retical writings of Mohandas Gandhi and Martin Luther King, Jr., that

      anger is not only not necessary for the pursuit of justice, but also a large

      impediment to the generosity and empathy that help to construct a future

      of justice. Anger may still have limited utility in the three instrumental

      ways I have identified (as signal, as motivation, and as deterrent), but

      it is crucial that the leader of a revolutionary movement, and many of

      the followers, be strange sorts of people, part Stoic and part creatures

      of love. Nonetheless there have been such leaders and followers, as the

      thought and life of Nelson Mandela demonstrate. And maybe they are

      not so strange after all, since human life does contain surprising stretches

      Introduction

      9

      of joy and generosity, qualities that go well with the project of building

      something better than what exists already.

      This clean division of realms is too simple, of course, because the

      realms intersect and influence one another in many ways. The family is

      a realm of love, but it is also a political institution shaped by law, and it contains many wrongs (such as rape, assault, and child abuse) that the

      law must take extremely seriously. Slights in the workplace (for exam-

      ple) are Middle Realm wrongs, but they may also be instances of racial

      or gender discrimination, of harassment, or of tortious negligence, thus

      bringing them within the ambit of the law, and of the sort of carefully

      limited Transition- Anger (the Eumenides in their new basement abode)

      that is proper to political wrongs. Moreover, our relationships with col-

      leagues, unlike relationships with strangers on airplanes and on the road,

      are ongoing relationships that have at least some weight and significance:

      so they lie between the full intimacy of love and friendship and the for-

      gettable encounter with a rude seatmate. Furthermore, as I have already

      emphasized, serious crimes against the person, such as assault, rape, and

      homicide by non- intimates, are serious wrongs and also legal offenses

      in the Middle Realm. The proper attitudes toward these wrongs, in their

     
    different aspects, will take a lot of sorting out.

      Equally important, the Political Realm is not simply a realm of

      impartial justice. If a nation is to survive and motivate people to care

      about the common good, the public realm will need some of the generos-

      ity and the non- inquisitorial spirit that I think of as proper to the personal realm, where keeping score of all one’s wrongs may be carried too far

      and poison the common endeavor. That, really, is the core of Aeschylus’

      insight: that instead of exporting to the city the vindictiveness and blood-

      thirstiness of the family at its worst, the city should draw on the bonds of

      trust and the emotions of loving generosity that characterize the family

      at its best.

      Although my central topic is anger and its proper management in the

      three realms, my project also has a subtheme, which involves a critical

      examination of one prominent candidate to replace anger as the central

      attitude in the area of wrongdoing. This substitute attitude is forgiveness,

      and its candidacy is vigorously championed in modern discussions. The

      concept of forgiveness is strikingly absent from the Eumenides, as, indeed, (I would say) from all of ancient Greek ethics,18 but it is so central to modern discussions of anger that one cannot approach the topic without grap-

      pling with it extensively. I therefore propose to do so here, addressing

      the familiar contention that forgiveness is a central political and personal

      virtue. At the end of the day we will be close, in at least some crucial

      respects, to where Aeschylus left us— but after clearing away a great deal

      that intervening centuries have bequeathed. Thus we will be able to see

      10

      Anger and Forgiveness

      more clearly what the insights of the Eumenides might offer to a modern world. Let me now introduce that subsidiary theme.

      We live in what is often described as a “culture of apology and for-

      giveness.”19 A cursory Amazon book search turns up scores of titles. Most

      are works of popular psychology and self- help. Frequently they couple

      the idea of forgiveness with that of a “journey” or a “road.” Taking this

      journey, usually guided by a therapist, the wronged person moves from

      some terrible place of pain to a lovely place of transfiguring happiness.

      My favorite such title is Breaking Night: A Memoir of Forgiveness, Survival, and My Journey from Homeless to Harvard.20 Imagine that. From the horrors of homelessness, and the anger one can imagine that life evoking in

     


    Prev Next
Online Read Free Novel Copyright 2016 - 2025